One of the best-known quotations from Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations (1776) defines natural liberty: “Every man, as long as he does not violate the laws of justice, is left perfectly free to pursue his own interest his own way, and to bring both his industry and capital into competition with those of any other man.”
Smith inserted the condition “so long as he does not violate the laws of justice” ahead of the directive because it was central to his conception of liberty. What everyone remembers is “free to pursue his own interest,” with the last often turned into “self-interest.” But Smith’s conception of human sociality and economy—I like the word “humanomics”—was far deeper than modern utilitarianism.
What did Smith mean by justice, and why is it so important for understanding his message? The carefully articulated answer was in his first book: The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759, pp. 78-91).
Justice for Smith was the negative of his proposition on injustice, which stated that improperly motivated (that is, intentionally) hurtful actions alone deserve punishment because they are the objects of a widely shared sense of resentment.
Rules that punished in proportion to resentment emerged naturally in pre-civil society as a means of defense only against real positive evil and to secure innocence and safeguard justice.
Hence, justice is a residual. Justice is the infinite set of permissible actions remaining after specifying the finite limited set of prohibited actions and corresponding penalties.
Imagine a large playing field in which people explore, discover, and innovate, but with well-defined foul boundaries that people are not to breach without penalty; these boundaries will change, based on consent, with experience, culture, and technology.
Smith saw society as seeking human socio-economic betterment through the control of actions that our common experience leads us to judge as hurtful rather than through collective actions designed to achieve future conjectured benefits. The latter is uncertain and fraught with unintended consequences; moreover, history is littered with examples of grandiose failures. The former relies on natural impulses for individuals and assemblies to pursue betterment, risking only their own resources; this framework led him to oppose slavery, colonialism, empire, mercantilism, and taxation without representation at a time when such views were unpopular.
His policy views derive from his belief that every person’s socio-economic achievements should depend as much as possible on merit and as little as possible on privilege.
Vernon L. Smith is Professor of Economics and Law at Chapman University. In 2002, he was awarded the Nobel Prize in Economic Sciences for his pioneering work in experimental economics.
This article was reprinted with permission of the publisher. “The Core of the Classical Liberal Tradition: Adam Smith’s Concept of Justice,” by Vernon Smith, http://blog.independent.org/2017/10/06/the-core-of-the-classical-liberal-tradition-adam-smiths-concept-of-justice/.
All rights reserved. Copyright 2017, Independent Institute, 100 Swan Way, Oakland, California 94621-1428; http://www.independent.org/; info@independent.org
Comment
|
October 16th, 2017
The Core of Classical Liberalism: Adam Smith’s Concept of Justice
by Vernon Smith
One of the best-known quotations from Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations (1776) defines natural liberty: “Every man, as long as he does not violate the laws of justice, is left perfectly free to pursue his own interest his own way, and to bring both his industry and capital into competition with those of any other man.”
Smith inserted the condition “so long as he does not violate the laws of justice” ahead of the directive because it was central to his conception of liberty. What everyone remembers is “free to pursue his own interest,” with the last often turned into “self-interest.” But Smith’s conception of human sociality and economy—I like the word “humanomics”—was far deeper than modern utilitarianism.
What did Smith mean by justice, and why is it so important for understanding his message? The carefully articulated answer was in his first book: The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759, pp. 78-91).
Justice for Smith was the negative of his proposition on injustice, which stated that improperly motivated (that is, intentionally) hurtful actions alone deserve punishment because they are the objects of a widely shared sense of resentment.
Rules that punished in proportion to resentment emerged naturally in pre-civil society as a means of defense only against real positive evil and to secure innocence and safeguard justice.
Hence, justice is a residual. Justice is the infinite set of permissible actions remaining after specifying the finite limited set of prohibited actions and corresponding penalties.
Imagine a large playing field in which people explore, discover, and innovate, but with well-defined foul boundaries that people are not to breach without penalty; these boundaries will change, based on consent, with experience, culture, and technology.
Smith saw society as seeking human socio-economic betterment through the control of actions that our common experience leads us to judge as hurtful rather than through collective actions designed to achieve future conjectured benefits. The latter is uncertain and fraught with unintended consequences; moreover, history is littered with examples of grandiose failures. The former relies on natural impulses for individuals and assemblies to pursue betterment, risking only their own resources; this framework led him to oppose slavery, colonialism, empire, mercantilism, and taxation without representation at a time when such views were unpopular.
His policy views derive from his belief that every person’s socio-economic achievements should depend as much as possible on merit and as little as possible on privilege.
Vernon L. Smith is Professor of Economics and Law at Chapman University. In 2002, he was awarded the Nobel Prize in Economic Sciences for his pioneering work in experimental economics.
Source: Independent Institute
This article was reprinted with permission of the publisher. “The Core of the Classical Liberal Tradition: Adam Smith’s Concept of Justice,” by Vernon Smith, http://blog.independent.org/2017/10/06/the-core-of-the-classical-liberal-tradition-adam-smiths-concept-of-justice/.
All rights reserved. Copyright 2017, Independent Institute, 100 Swan Way, Oakland, California 94621-1428; http://www.independent.org/; info@independent.org
Author
View all posts
The views expressed on austriancenter.com are not necessarily those of the Austrian Economics Center.
Do you like the article?
We are glad you do! Please consider donating if you want to read more articles like this one.
Related
Comment
In Rational Selfie Interest
September 9th, 2015
Comment
It’s the Austrians’ season! – Books for Christmas
December 9th, 2019
Comment
The Myth of the Failed Roaring Twenties
November 16th, 2020
Comment
Brazil's Bread and Circuses
May 14th, 2014
Comment
The Nation State Offers No Solutions for the Future
March 2nd, 2020